nouamanetazi HF staff commited on
Commit
d34c748
1 Parent(s): 34d38fb

Upload raw/train/22/1567162622.json

Browse files
Files changed (1) hide show
  1. raw/train/22/1567162622.json +1 -0
raw/train/22/1567162622.json ADDED
@@ -0,0 +1 @@
 
 
1
+ {"source_url": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org", "url": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/article/making-emergency-use-experimental-vaccines-safer/2020-01", "title": "Making Emergency Use of Experimental Vaccines Safer", "top_image": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/themes/custom/ama_joe_theme/favicon.ico", "meta_img": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/themes/custom/ama_joe_theme/favicon.ico", "images": ["https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/sites/journalofethics.ama-assn.org/files/styles/teaser_image_style_450x225_/public/2019-11/cscm1-2001.jpg?itok=YPH3GxYA", "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/themes/custom/ama_joe_theme/favicon.ico", "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/sites/journalofethics.ama-assn.org/files/styles/teaser_image_style_450x225_/public/2019-11/cscm3-2001.jpg?itok=AlTvN6D4", "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/themes/custom/ama_joe_theme/images/brand/logo.svg", "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/sites/journalofethics.ama-assn.org/files/styles/teaser_image_style_450x225_/public/2019-11/artm1-2001.jpg?itok=lCu7eJhe", "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/sites/journalofethics.ama-assn.org/files/styles/teaser_image_style_450x225_/public/2019-11/nlit1-2001.jpg?itok=HbvYpOk2"], "movies": [], "text": "Abstract\n\nEthical and logistical challenges of deploying experimental vaccines in humanitarian emergencies are exacerbated by a paucity of safety and efficacy data. For outbreaks caused by pathogens with high mortality rates and few treatments, such as Ebola virus disease, not offering access to experimental vaccines with some evidence of efficacy can also be ethically suspect. This article recommends (1) gathering more preclinical data about experimental vaccines\u2019 safety and (2) improving research infrastructure to enable participation of a wide range of subjects in affected communities over long trial periods. Motivating these goals would facilitate clearer definitions of population vulnerability and risk acceptability.\n\nRisk of Disease vs Risk of Experimental Vaccination\n\nSafe and effective vaccination programs are critical to mitigating disease outbreaks, but vaccine deployment can be fraught with logistical challenges and ethical questions that vary with the environments in which programs are implemented. Effectively deploying experimental vaccines for emerging infectious diseases relies on policy and research infrastructure to ensure safe, ethical research during emergencies. The complexity of these challenges was apparent during the management of recent Ebola virus disease (EVD) epidemics. At the time of the 2013-2016 West African outbreak, effective management was hampered by, among other things, a lack of licensed vaccines and treatments to deploy to control EVD.1,2 In the midst of global community members\u2019 push to initiate clinical trials for experimental vaccines and therapeutics, discussions arose about which criteria should be used to distribute experimental vaccines among vulnerable groups, particularly those in resource-limited settings.3 The current North Kivu EVD outbreak in the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC) suggests a continuing need to consider distribution criteria and to develop strategies for anticipating and addressing ethical and logistical questions.\n\nDuring recent EVD outbreaks, whether experimental recombinant vesicular stomatitis virus-based vaccine (rVSV-ZEBOV) should be used in pregnant and lactating women and in children under one year of age has raised ethical questions. During the 2013-2016 West African Ebola epidemic, members of these populations were excluded from Ebola \u00e7a Suffit! trials.4 Although the World Health Organization (WHO) Research Ethics Review Committee guided implementation of trials during that outbreak and requested amendments to the protocol to include members of these populations as subjects, it later relented, as further review was seen as delaying trial initiation and \u201cpotential benefit for all.\u201d5 In 2019, the DRC National Ethics Committee approved inclusion of pregnant or lactating women and children in a large experimental rVSV vaccination campaign that was underway but required close follow-up and limited distribution to areas where Ebola was being actively transmitted.6 This committee\u2019s decision highlights that comparing vulnerable community members\u2019 risk of harm from EVD to their risk of harm from rVSV tends to be considered in decisions about whether, where, and with whom to use experimental vaccines.\n\nA first question to ask about experimental vaccine administration among vulnerable populations in emergent situations is this: How should the concept of vulnerability be defined? Individual, social, cultural, and scientific variables should be prioritized in a definition of this concept and considered with reference to a specific situation or circumstance. We argue that members of vulnerable populations can more safely participate in experimental vaccine trials that (1) gather preclinical data and (2) bolster research infrastructure that enables diverse enrollment and long-term follow-up.\n\nDefining Vulnerability\n\nIn research ethics, a vulnerable population is generally thought to be one whose members\u2019 ability to consent to participate in a research protocol is compromised (eg, through lack of competency, illiteracy, poverty, or inability to communicate). A Canadian Tri-Council Policy Statement (TCPS2) more generally defines vulnerability as \u201cdiminished ability to fully safeguard one\u2019s own interests in the context of a specific research project\u201d due to \u201climited decision-making capacity or limited access to social goods, such as rights, opportunity, and power.\u201d7 Vulnerability \u201cmay require greater effort to minimize risks to participants and/or maximize potential benefits\u201d in order that they be treated justly.8\n\nMore often than not, members of populations considered vulnerable are excluded from clinical trials.\n\nApplying this definition of vulnerability responsibly requires considering that observers can differ in their perceptions of a subject\u2019s moral agency.9 For example, during an outbreak, individuals or communities might not perceive themselves as vulnerable, although regulatory bodies or health care organizations do, and vice versa. Moreover, simply identifying characteristics that confer \u201cvulnerability\u201d can also be challenging largely because they can consist of both individual traits\u2014including young age, ethnicity, race, gender, or general or mental health status\u2014and particular contexts that apply to an entire community.\n\nHow we define vulnerability shapes how those seen as vulnerable are treated and influences opportunities they are offered. As examples, the Ebola \u00e7a Suffit! trial prioritized vaccination for subjects exposed to the virus who were not pregnant, breastfeeding, or severely ill; other trials have included health care workers as subjects, excluding pregnant or lactating women.4 More often that not, members of populations considered vulnerable are excluded from clinical trials.10 Although pregnant women tend to suffer high mortality from EVD,11 they and members of other groups have been excluded from clinical EVD trials.11 Recently, there has been a shift toward not labeling populations as vulnerable,11,12 but removing protections justly and equitably requires input and buy-in from members of these populations, which is difficult to accomplish during an outbreak.\n\nEVD outbreaks have occurred\u2014and continue to occur\u2014in settings fraught with armed conflict and displacement,14 which exacerbate individuals\u2019 and communities\u2019 vulnerability. Postconflict food insecurity and lack of health care infrastructure in West Africa likely heightened susceptibility to EVD during the 2014 epidemic and helped propagate it.15,16 These conditions persist in the ongoing epidemic in the DRC, where conflict has made tracing contacts difficult, complexified vaccine investigation, and led some to switch to mass vaccination strategies. Such factors must contextualize how we define and understand concepts such as vulnerability and even emergency, which the WHO defines as the co-existence of outbreak along with either a man-made or natural condition that could cause disruption to health care services.17 Since context can be dynamic, the process of defining key concepts should also be dynamic. Therefore, international and local agencies should develop close relationships with communities to keep abreast of geopolitical shifts that might influence assessments of vulnerability.\n\nThe state of medical science related to emerging diseases like EVD also matters to how vulnerability is defined. A change in clinical standards of care for a particular disease that alters the risk-benefit profile used in individuals\u2019 and agencies\u2019 decision making should also be regarded as a key variable in understanding and defining vulnerability. For example, populations\u2019 susceptibility to EVD during the 2013-2016 epidemic largely hinged on lack of alternatives to experimental drugs to prevent and treat EVD, which likely affected subjects\u2019 decision making about whether to participate in trials. New therapeutic and investigational vaccines have emerged since then,18 which have altered risk-benefit profiles of communities undergoing an epidemic and will likewise critically shape conceptions of vulnerability. The changing medical context suggests the importance of determinations of vulnerability being made and reassessed continuously by regulatory committees or global health organizations with regular input from affected communities.\n\nInclusion and Safety\n\nSeveral reports, including a recent review by the Pregnancy Research Ethics for Vaccines, Epidemics, and New Technologies (PREVENT) Working Group, highlight how exclusion of vulnerable groups, including pregnant women and children, from research can result in their not having access to experimental vaccines during emergencies.19 This report\u2019s key recommendations for including pregnant women in vaccine research set good milestones to follow for research with other vulnerable populations, however defined in a particular situation.\n\nGather preclinical data on safety of experimental vaccine use in vulnerable populations. The PREVENT group recommends using advanced technology to study immune responses of pregnant women and children and recommends creation of market incentives to include vulnerable subgroups in research.19 These efforts should also seek to augment knowledge about use of experimental vaccines in persons with HIV and highly prevalent co-infections that might lead to biological vulnerability to disease.6 Enable safe enrollment of vulnerable subjects in vaccine trials during crises. Reports have stressed the importance of building surveillance and health information systems to allow improved capture of the outcomes of experimental vaccine deployment, particularly in vulnerable populations.19,20 Aside from strengthening national health systems, building research capacity in countries where Ebola and other pathogens on the WHO\u2019s priority diseases list pose risk can motivate safe deployment of experimental vaccines during outbreaks.21 A review of clinical trials conducted during the 2013-2016 EVD epidemic by a committee of the National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine suggests the importance of long-standing research engagement to enable timely deployment of investigational agents in communities at risk.22 Cultivate long-term, trusting relationships. The WHO has developed a framework for ethical decision making concerning use of experimental vaccines during emergencies.17,23 In addition, perceptions of risks and benefits of groups considered to be vulnerable should inform community participation strategies. One recent study found that many subjects in an Ebola vaccine trial were motivated by altruism, curiosity, hope, health seeking, and notions of exchange.24 Understanding the role of these values in subjects\u2019 decisions about whether to enroll in a protocol suggest that engagement with local leaders and decision makers is key when discussing experimental vaccine deployment in an emergency and is critical for motivating trust. Due to mistrust, 2 Ebola vaccine trials were suspended in Ghana.25\n\nConclusions\n\nEthical questions about deploying experimental vaccines during recent and ongoing EVD outbreaks are complex and multifaceted and require attention to dynamic context. Navigating collaborative responses to these questions is aided by contextualizing definitions of vulnerability and emergency; preparedness; nourishing ongoing and sustainable partnerships with people in local communities where outbreaks tend to recur, including through developing trusting communication; and investing in research infrastructure.", "keywords": [], "meta_keywords": [""], "tags": [], "authors": ["Archana", "Nahid"], "publish_date": "Wed Jan 1 00:00:00 2020", "summary": "", "article_html": "", "meta_description": "How would gathering preclinical data and improving research infrastructure facilitate clearer definitions of \u201cpopulation vulnerability\u201d and \u201crisk acceptability\u201d?", "meta_lang": "", "meta_favicon": "/themes/custom/ama_joe_theme/favicon.ico", "meta_data": {"citation_reference": "citation_title=Ethical considerations for vaccination programmes in acute humanitarian emergencies\r\n;citation_author=Moodley K;citation_author=Hardie K;citation_author=Selgelid MJ;citation_author=et al;citation_journal_title=Bull World Health Organ\r\n;citation_volume=91;citation_issue=4;citation_number=4;citation_publication_date=2020;citation_firstpage=290;citation_lastpage=297;", "citation_author": "Nahid Bhadelia", "citation_fulltext_world_readable": "", "title": "Making Emergency Use of Experimental Vaccines Safer | Journal of Ethics | American Medical Association", "citation_title": "Making Emergency Use of Experimental Vaccines Safer", "twitter": {"card": "summary", "description": "How would gathering preclinical data and improving research infrastructure facilitate clearer definitions of \u201cpopulation vulnerability\u201d and \u201crisk acceptability\u201d?", "image": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/sites/journalofethics.ama-assn.org/files/2019-11/stas1-2001.jpg"}, "citation_abstract": "not offering access to experimental vaccines with some evidence of efficacy can also be ethically suspect. This article recommends (1) gathering more preclinical data about experimental vaccines\u2019 safety and (2) improving research infrastructure to enable participation of a wide range of subjects in affected communities over long trial periods. Motivating these goals would facilitate clearer definitions of population vulnerability and risk acceptability.", "og": {"site_name": "Journal of Ethics | American Medical Association", "url": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/article/making-emergency-use-experimental-vaccines-safer/2020-01", "title": "Making Emergency Use of Experimental Vaccines Safer", "description": "How would gathering preclinical data and improving research infrastructure facilitate clearer definitions of \u201cpopulation vulnerability\u201d and \u201crisk acceptability\u201d?", "image": {"url": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/sites/journalofethics.ama-assn.org/files/2019-11/stas1-2001.jpg"}}, "citation_fulltext_html_url": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/article/making-emergency-use-experimental-vaccines-safer/2020-01", "citation_publisher": "American Medical Association", "citation_publication_date": "2020-01-01", "description": "How would gathering preclinical data and improving research infrastructure facilitate clearer definitions of \u201cpopulation vulnerability\u201d and \u201crisk acceptability\u201d?", "citation_doi": "10.1001/amajethics.2020.43.", "citation_journal_title": "AMA Journal of Ethics", "google-site-verification": "TBbitFF4VJF1paIv0qHbeEV-7EQ58PPXk8hamar5DkQ", "citation_issn": "2376-6980", "citation_volume": 22, "citation_issue": 1, "citation_firstpage": 43, "citation_lastpage": 49, "citation_pdf_url": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/sites/journalofethics.ama-assn.org/files/2019-12/stas1-2001_1.pdf", "Generator": "Drupal 8 (https://www.drupal.org)", "MobileOptimized": "width", "HandheldFriendly": "true", "viewport": "width=device-width, initial-scale=1.0"}, "canonical_link": "https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/article/making-emergency-use-experimental-vaccines-safer/2020-01"}